A disconcerting issue has hit the political radar: male
circumcision. Is it a medical procedure or child abuse?
As furor over
female
genital mutilation grows, so does the criticism of male
circumcision.
This June, Arizona eliminated Medicaid funding for infant
circumcision, following the lead of six other states:
California, Oregon, Washington, Nevada, North Dakota, and
Mississippi. In July, a
North
Dakota court ruled that an adult male could sue the doctor
who circumcised him even though the parents had consented and
there was no "botch." Flatt v. Kantak became the latest
in a series of
circumcision
cases that test the legal status of the procedure.
Circumcision has been under attack for the last few years. In
1999, the American Academy of Pediatrics
revised
its guidelines to state, "the benefits are not significant
enough for the AAP to recommend circumcision as a routine
procedure." In 2000, the American Medical Association
modified
its policy to read, "Existing scientific evidence
demonstrates potential medical benefits ... however, these data
are not sufficient to recommend routine neonatal
circumcision."
Yet most male babies in
North
America continue to be circumcised. Advocates loudly
proclaim its advantages for men, including an HIV-protective
effect for men, and its benefits for women — those with
circumcised partners are said to have a reduced risk of
cervical
cancer.
Yet the central question keeps returning: Is the removal of
any part of a healthy sexual organ justified?
The passionate debate has implications far wider than
medicine. One is equality under the law. Female genitalia
mutilation is already a criminal act under Title 18
United States Code
Section 116, which reads, in part, "whoever knowingly
circumcises, excises, or infibulates the whole or any
part of the labia majora or labia minora or clitoris of
another person who has not attained the age of 18 years shall be
fined under this title or imprisoned not more than five years,
or both." [Emphasis added.]
Procedures necessary to health are excluded.
To remove any part of healthy male genitalia would seem to be
an act parallel in law to female genital mutilation. Indeed, the
plaintiff in Flatt v. Kantak will probably argue along
these lines.
What does this mean for
Jewish
ritual circumcision, called Brit Milah — a sign of the
Jewish covenant with God? The U.S. Code against mutilating
female genitalia makes no exception for religion or culture. It
states, "no account shall be taken of the effect on the person
on whom the operation is to be performed of any belief on the
part of that person, or any other person, that the operation is
required as a matter of custom or ritual."
If variations of Islamic religion and culture do not justify
mutilating women, then can religion justify non-therapeutic male
circumcision? Nothing in international or domestic law would
seem to allow the discriminatory banning of only female genital
mutilation. Indeed, for decades, international law has come down
against routine circumcision. For example, the U.N.'s
Universal
Declaration of Human Rights (1948) speaks of the "human
rights" involved in "the ethics of circumcision," which are "the
rights to security of person, to freedom from torture and other
cruel and unusual treatment, and to privacy."
Those who claim that the mutilation of female genitalia
cannot be likened to circumcision should read the many
anti-circumcision
sites that offer horror stories.
Mothers
Against Circumcision claim that these "side effects" are not
uncommon and that circumcision has inherent and universal
disadvantages, such as a diminishment of sexual pleasure.
Circumcision is also a moral issue. The organization
Doctors
Opposing Circumcision decries the procedure as "painful,"
"tragic," "contra-indicated," and states "that no one has the
right to forcibly remove sexual body parts from another
individual." DOC claims that circumcision violates the
physician's Golden Rule — First, Do No Harm — as well as all
seven principles of the A.M.A. Code of Ethics.
These are merely some of the political and moral questions
surrounding circumcision. For better or worse, the parameters of
this issue may well be determined in the courts through lawyers'
arguments and judges' decisions. Which brings us back to
Flatt v. Kantak.
Unfortunately, this case muddies the discussion by
introducing other significant issues. For example, since the
parents consented, the case implicitly asks whether parents have
a right to make decisions about their children's bodies. Or is
the real issue "informed consent"? Do doctors need to fully
reveal all the possible side effects of, current thinking on and
alternatives to circumcision, so that it is no longer "routine"?
On the other hand, if circumcision is legally shown to be a
form of criminal harm, then the "informed consent" of parents
may be irrelevant: doctors, nurses, hospitals, and mohels might
be held criminally liable, alongside parents, for child abuse.
As medical associations one-by-one refuse to support routine
circumcision, the procedure is losing ground — medically,
morally, politically, and legally. This process is being sped
along by aggressive groups like
The National Organization of
Circumcision Information Resource Centers, a "non-profit
educational organization committed to securing the birthright of
male and female children and babies to keep their sexual organs
intact."
The ensuing debate will help define medical ethics for a new
generation.